Nietzsche, Godfather of Fascism? On the Uses and Abuses of a Philosophy (Sample Chapter for Golomb, J. and Wistrich, R.S., eds.)

via Sample Chapter for Golomb, J. and Wistrich, R.S., eds.: Nietzsche, Godfather of Fascism? On the Uses and Abuses of a Philosophy..

Introduction

Jacob Golomb and Robert S. Wistrich

Nietzsche and fascism? Is it not almost a contradiction in terms? What can Nietzsche have in common with this murderous ideology? The central ideal of Nietzsche’s philosophy was the individual and his freedom to shape his own character and destiny. The German philosopher was frequently described as the “radical aristocrat” of the spirit because he abhorred mass culture and strove to cultivate a special kind of human being, the Übermensch, endowed with exceptional spiritual and mental qualities. What can such a thinker have in common with National Socialism’s manipulation of the masses for chauvinistic goals that swallowed up the personalities, concerns, and life of the individual?

In 1934, Adolf Hitler paid a much publicized visit to the Nietzsche archives at Weimar. He had gone at the insistent request of its director, Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche (sister of the long-deceased German philosopher), and he was accompanied by his personal photographer, Heinrich Hoffmann. The main purpose of the visit, it seems, was to enable Hoffmann to take a picture of Hitler contemplating the bust of Nietzsche, which stood in the reception room. Perhaps appropriately, only half of the philosopher’s head was shown in the picture, which duly appeared in the German press with a caption that read, “The Führer before the bust of the German philosopher whose ideas have fertilized two great popular movements: the National Socialism of Germany and the Fascist movement of Italy.”

Although Benito Mussolini was certainly familiar with Nietzsche’s writings and was a long-time admirer of the philosopher, Hitler’s own connection with Nietzsche remains uncertain. As a soldier during the First World War, he had carried the works of Schopenhauer and not those of Nietzsche in his backpack. There is no reference to Nietzsche in Mein Kampf (though there is to Schopenhauer), and in Hitlers Table Talk, he refers only indirectly to Nietzsche, saying: “In our part of the world, the Jews would have immediately eliminated Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and Kant. If the Bolsheviks had dominion over us for two hundred years, what works of our past would be handed on to posterity? Our great men would fall into oblivion, or else they’d be presented to future generations as criminals and bandits.”1

Thus the picture of Hitler gazing at Nietzsche’s bust had more to do with a carefully orchestrated cult, one aspect of which was to connect National Socialism with the philosopher’s legacy, at least by association. On October 1944, celebrating the hundredth anniversary of the birth of Nietzsche, Alfred Rosenberg, the leading Nazi party ideologist, delivered an official speech in Weimar, seeking to reinforce this impression: “In a truly historical sense, the National Socialist movement eclipses the rest of the world, much as Nietzsche, the individual, eclipsed the powers of his times.”2 Of course, Nietzsche was not the only German philosopher invoked as a spiritual guide and forerunner of the Nazi revolution, but his “Nazification” in the course of the Third Reich is a historical fact that cannot be denied, though it is more open to interpretation than is sometimes assumed.

The intriguing question that lies at the heart of this original collection of essays is how Nietzsche came to acquire the deadly “honor” of being considered the philosopher of the Third Reich and whether such claims have any justification. What was it in Nietzsche that attracted such a Nazi appropriation in the first place? To what extent is it legitimate to view Nietzsche as a protofascist thinker? Does it make any sense to hold him in some way responsible for the horrors of Auschwitz? These issues are not as clear-cut as they may seem, and though they have attracted much polemical heat, they have not received any truly systematic treatment. In this volume, we have attempted to fill that gap in as concise and comprehensive a way as possible by turning to a variety of distinguished historians, Nietzsche scholars, philosophers, and historians of ideas. It was clear from the outset that we could not expect, nor indeed did we strive for, unanimous conclusions on the thorny, complex, and emotionally charged question of Nietzsche and fascism. A whole range of views is presented here that attempts to do justice in different ways to the ambiguity and richness of Nietzsche’s thought. Nietzsche encouraged his readers to shift their intellectual viewpoints and be willing to experience even radically incompatible perspectives. Thus by dealing with the subject matter of this collection from two different perspectives–that of philosophers and of historians–we hope that a Nietzschean spirit of intellectual tolerance will be reflected in this volume.

Nietzsche’s life and thought will never be reducible to a single constituency or political ideology, as this volume makes plain. The ambiguities and contradictions in his work as well as his elusive, aphoristic style lend themselves to a wide range of meanings and a multiplicity of interpretations. Nevertheless, while acknowledging this diversity, the editors cannot in good conscience be exempted from the challenge of offering some guidelines regarding the central issues raised by a book about Nietzsche and fascism, even if the title (as seems appropriate in this case) ends with a question mark.

Nietzsche was clearly an elitist who believed in the right to rule of a “good and healthy aristocracy,” one that would, if necessary, be ready to sacrifice untold numbers of human beings. He sometimes wrote as if nations primarily existed for the sake of producing a few “great men,” who could not be expected to show consideration for “normal humanity.” Not suprisingly, in the light of the cruel century that has just ended, one is bound to regard such statements with grave misgivings. From Mussolini and Hitler to Stalin, Mao, Pol Pot, and Saddam Hussein, the last eighty years have been riddled with so-called political geniuses imagining that they were “beyond good and evil” and free of any moral constraints. One has to ask if there is not something in Nietzsche’s philosophy with its uninhibited cultivation of a heroic individualism and the will to power, which may have tended to favor the fascist ethos. Musssolini, for example, raised the Nietzschean formulation “live dangerously” (vivi pericolosamente) to the status of a fascist slogan. His reading of Nietzsche was one factor in converting him from Marxism to a philosophy of sacrifice and warlike deeds in defense of the fatherland. In this mutation, Mussolini was preceded by Gabriele d’Annunzio, whose passage from aestheticism to the political activism of a new, more virile and warlike age, was (as Mario Sznajder points out in his essay) greatly influenced by Nietzsche. Equally, there were other representatives of the First World War generation, like the radical German nationalist writer, Ernst Jünger, who would find in Nietzsche’s writings a legitimization of the warrior ethos (as David Ohana makes clear).

There have also been Marxist critics like George Lukács, who saw in Nietzsche’s philosophy nothing more than an ideological apologia for the rapacious plunder of German capitalist imperialism and a particularly destructive form of irrationalism. Lukács insisted both on the reactionary coherence of Nietzsche’s “system” and on the “barren chaos” of his arbitrary language, singling him out as one of the most dangerous “intellectual class-enemies” of socialism. Lukács’s own miserable record as an apologist (for the crimes of Stalinism), gave his one-sided reading of Nietzsche (which equated hostility to egalitarian socialism with fascist imperialism) transparently propagandist coloring, yet it is an interpretation that had considerable influence in its day.

Many commentators have raised the question as to whether the vulgar exploitation of Nietzsche by fascists, militarists, and Nazis could indeed be altogether arbitrary. While almost any philosophy can be propagandistically abused (as Hans Sluga has shown, Kant was a particular favorite among academic philosophers of the Third Reich!), Nietzsche’s pathos, his imaginative excesses as well as his image as a prophetseer and creator of myths, seems especially conducive to such abuse by fascists. The radical manner in which Nietzsche thrust himself against the boundaries of conventional (Judeo-Christian) morality and dramatically proclaimed that God (meaning the bourgeois Christian faith of the nineteenth century) was dead, undoubtedly appealed to something in Nazism that wished to transgress and transcend all existing taboos. The totalitarianism of the twentieth century (of both the Right and Left) presupposed a breakdown of all authority and moral norms, of which Nietzsche was indeed a clear-sighted prophet, precisely because he had diagnosed nihilism as the central problem of his society–that of fin de si`ecle Europe. For him there was no way back to the old moral certainties about “good” and “evil,” no way to regain firm ground under one’s feet. Humanity, long before 1914, had (spiritually speaking) already burned its bridges. Nietzsche was convinced that there was no escape from the “nihilism” of the age, except to go forward into a more “perfect nihilism,” to use the term of Wolfgang Müller-Lauter in this volume. Nietzsche believed that only by honestly facing the stark truth that there is no truth, no goal, no value or meaning in itself, could one pave the way for a real intellectual liberation and a revaluation of all values. Nietzsche was more a herald and prophet of the crisis of values out of which Nazism emerged, rather than a godfather of the century’s fascist movements per se.

Much of the confusion identifying Nietzsche with National Socialism can be traced back to the disastrous role of his sister Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche (married to a prominent German anti-Semite) who took control of his manuscripts in the 1890s, when he was mentally and physically incapacitated. Already in the 1920s she promoted her brother as the philosopher of fascism, sending her warmest good wishes to Benito Mussolini as “the inspired reawakener of aristocratic values in Nietzsche’s sense”; similarly, she invited Hitler several times to the archive in Weimar, even giving him the symbolic gift of Nietzsche’s walking stick in 1934. Nazi propaganda encouraged such (mis)appropriation, for example, by publishing popular and inexpensive anthologies and short collections of Nietzsche’s sayings, which were then misused in their truncated form to promote militarism, toughness, and Germanic values. Alfred Bäumler, a professor of philosophy in Berlin after 1933, on seeing German youth march under the swastika banner could even write, “[A]nd when we call ‘Heil Hitler!’ to this youth then we are greeting at the same time Friedrich Nietzsche with that call.” Needless to say, Bäumler played a key role in the increasingly shameless appropriation of Nietzsche as a philosopher of the so-called Nordic race, a kind of intellectual Siegfried–anti-Roman, anti-Christian (which was true), and thoroughly in tune with the spirit of 1914. Aware that Nietzsche had no theory of volk or race, Bäumler nonetheless concocted a spurious link between the philosopher’s individual struggle for integrity and Nazi collectivism. With the same sleight of hand, he could explain away Nietzsche’s break with Wagner merely as a product of envy and dismiss his tirades against the Germans as expressing no more than his disapproval of certain non-Germanic elements in their character.

No less convoluted were the efforts of the Nazi commentator Heinrich Härtle in his 1937 book Nietzsche und der Nationalsozialismus, where he presented the philosopher “as a great ally in the present spiritual warfare.” Härtle realized that Nietzsche’s advocacy of European unity, his elitism and individualism, his critique of the state, his approval of race-mixing, and his anti-anti-Semitism were incompatible with Nazi ideology. By relativizing these shortcomings as minor issues (in the case of the Jews, he simply quoted those instances–comparatively few in number–where Nietzsche seemed to be attacking them) and as reflections of a different political environment in the nineteenth century, Härtle could present Nietzsche as a precursor of Hitler.

Sadly, such crude distortions were echoed in Allied war propaganda and in newspaper headlines in Britain and the United States, which (continuing the traditions of the First World War) sometimes depicted the “insane philosopher” as the source of a ruthless German barbarism and as Hitler’s favorite author. Phrases torn out of their context such as the “superman,” (or “Overman”), the “blond beast,” “master morality,” or the “will to power” were all too easily turned into slogans (even by distinguished philosophers like Sir Karl Popper3) to demonstrate Nietzsche’s imagined identification with German militarism and imperialism, though nothing had been further from his mind.

Before 1939 not everyone shared this increasingly broad consensus, which saw Nietzsche as the spiritual godfather of fascism and Nazism. Opponents of Nazism like the German philosophers Karl Jaspers and Karl Löwith sought to invalidate the official Nazi appropriation of Nietzsche in the 1930s. Together with a number of French intellectuals, they contributed to a special issue of Acéphale published in January 1937 and entitled “Réparation à Nietzsche.” The most prominent of the French antifascist Nietzscheans was the left-wing existentialist thinker Georges Bataille, who sought to rescue Nietzsche by demonstrating the German philosopher’s abhorrence of pan-Germanism, racism and the rabid anti-Semitism of Hitler’s followers. In the United States, the most eminent postwar advocate of a “liberal” Nietzsche was Walter Kaufmann, an American scholar in Princeton who provided many of the most authoritative translations into English of Nietzsche’s writings. His Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist (1950) became a standard work in the critical rehabilitation of Nietzsche in the postwar English-speaking world, seeking to dissociate him from any connection with Social Darwinism and the intellectual origins of National Socialism.

One of Kaufmann’s virtues was to document the scale of Nietzsche’s contempt for the racist anti-Semites of his generation, such as the schoolteacher Bernhard Förster (his sister’s husband), Theodor Fritsch, Paul de Lagarde, and Eugen Dühring. If Nazism conceived of Jewry as an inferior race of “subhumans” marked for annihilation, then Nietzsche’s own writings show, as both Yirmiyahu Yovel and Robert Wistrich have argued, that the Jews represented for him a kind of spiritual crystallization of what he understood by the Übermensch (Overman) of the future.

At first sight, this sharp rejection of anti-Semitism might seem a good enough reason to answer negatively and decisively the question concerning Nietzsche’s responsibility for Nazism. Certainly, a thinker who held a high opinion of Jewish qualities, looked to them as a spearhead for his own free-thinking Dionysian “revaluation of all values,” and sought their full integration into European society could hardly be blamed for the Nazi Holocaust. On the other hand, in his sweeping rejection of Judeo-Christian values (as they were mirrored in German Protestantism) Nietzsche constantly referred to their origin in the sublime “vengefulness” of Israel and its alleged exploitation of so-called movements of “decadence” (like early Christianity, liberalism, and socialism) to ensure its own self-preservation and survival (Menahem Brinker). Even though Nietzsche’s prime target was clearly Christianity–which he also blamed for the suffering of the Jews–the source of the infection ultimately lay in that fateful transvaluation of values initiated by priestly Judaism two millennia ago. It was a selective reading of this Nietzschean indictment of Judeo-Christianity that led the late Jacob Talmon, an Israeli historian, some forty years ago to see in Nietzsche a major intellectual signpost on the road to Auschwitz. Moreover, even when describing the “Judaization” of the world in terms that mixed admiration with disapprobation, Nietzsche seemed inadvertently to be feeding the myth of Jewish power, so beloved of Christian and racist anti-Semites. Though his intentions were profoundly hostile to anti-Semitism, this provocative technique was undoubtedly a dangerous game to play. While it would be senseless to hold Nietzsche responsible for such distortions, one can find troubling echoes of a vulgarized and debased Nietzscheanism in the later diatribes of Hitler, Himmler, Bormann, and Rosenberg against Judeo-Christianity.

The case of Nietzsche is a good illustration of the pitfalls in an overly schematic approach to intellectual history that takes particular strands in a thinker’s oeuvre and seeks to fit them into more general constructs like fascism or National Socialism. On the basis of Nietzsche’s declared hostility to Christianity, liberal democracy, and socialism, it is possible to see him as a precursor of the fascist synthesis. Some aspects of his admiration for ancient Greek culture and for “Romanitas” were used by both fascists and Nazis, who thoroughly distorted his philosophical intent. Though he took the ancient Greeks as cultural models, he did not subscribe to their self-conception as a “breed of masters,” which prompted them to brand non-Greeks as “barbarians,” fit only to be slaves. Indeed, all forms of xenophobia were profoundly alien to Nietzsche’s outlook, none more so than the hot-headed nationalistic rivalries so typical of the European nation-state system into which he was born. This explains his revulsion from the German nationalism that had come into vogue in the 1880s following the unification of Germany and the success of Bismarckian power politics. In fact, Nietzsche was in many respects the least patriotic and least German of his philosophical contemporaries in the Second Reich.

This was one of the major reasons for his abandonment of Wagner and the Bayreuth Festival, which had degenerated into a chauvinist celebration of “German Art,” “German virtues,” and a so-called “Germanic essence,” deeply contaminated by “the humbug of races” and antiSemitism. The fact that the Wagnerites gave a romantic Christian veneer to their cult of “Germanism” further provoked his antagonism. Nietzsche reserved a special animus for the ways in which the Christian churches in Germany had allowed themselves to be swept along by the national intoxication after 1870. Above all he denounced the corruption of the German “spirit” by the new practitioners of power politics. Hence it was one of the worst Nazi distortions of Nietzsche’s philosophy to claim that his notion of “the will to power” was consonant with what was being advocated in the Third Reich.

Far from relating to nationalist obsessions, Nietzsche had asserted a life-affirming outlook that sought to empower the individual to overcome his or her limitations by questioning all our assumptions concerning truth, logic, beliefs, culture, values, and history. As Jacob Golomb has shown, what Nietzsche prized above all was spiritual power (Macht) not the brute political force (Kraft) that he denounced with all the sarcasm at his command. This spiritual power of the sovereign, emancipated individual who is “master of a free will” involved a long and difficult process of sublimation, which would eventually culminate in self-mastery. It was a vision fundamentally antithetical to the totalitarian collectivism of both the Right and the Left.

Nietzsche’s indictment of the Christian and nationalist Right as well as of the official Machtpolitik and its consequences for German culture, was unequivocal. The break with Wagner is especially illuminating because the Wagnerian ideology and the cult that developed in Bayreuth was a much more real precursor of völkisch and Hitlerian ideas. Once Nietzsche had thrown off the romantic nationalism of his early days, his devastating critique of Wagner–prophetic in many ways of what was to come–revealed his remarkably penetrating insight into its dangerous illusions. National Socialism could plausibly derive inspiration from Wagner but it could only use Nietzsche by fundamentally twisting his philosophy.

Nietzsche was undeniably mobilized by the Nazis as several historical essays in the present collection demonstrate. So what exactly was the role of Nietzsche and his writings in this process? Is Martin Jay right to claim in his Fin-de-Siécle Socialism (1988) that “while it may be questionable to saddle Marx with responsibility for the Gulag archipelago or blame Nietzsche for Auschwitz, it is nevertheless true that their writings could be misread as justifications for these horrors in a way that . . . John Stuart Mill or Alexis de Toqueville could not” (33). Even Jacques Derrida, despite insisting that “Nietzsche’s utterances are not the same as those of the Nazi ideologists and not only because the latter grossly caricature the former to the point of apishness,” cannot refrain from wondering, in reference to Nietzsche’s case, “how and why what is so naively called a falsification was possible (one can’t falsify anything).”4

Some of the essays in the present collection try to answer this intriguing question. The enigma becomes even more perplexing in an argument in which a distinguished scholar absolves Nietzsche from any responsibility for the atrocities performed by the Nazis, yet holds him accountable for their misinterpretations. His claim is that Nietzsche had anticipated being misinterpreted as a fascist without doing enough to prevent these misinterpretations. Such a view is presented in Berel Lang’s essay. Yet, in his 1990 book, Lang asserts that “to reconstruct in the imagination the events leading up to the Nazi genocide against the Jews without the name or presence of Nietzsche is to be compelled to change almost nothing else in that pattern.”5 So who is right? Lang ten years ago or the essay we have included? Can we, indeed ever reach a definite and sound judgment concerning Nietzsche’s accountability, responsibility, or even culpability for Nazi misappropriations of his writings?

The essays below strive to provide us with some answers. But other, even more crucial questions hover over this issue. Was Nietzsche not trying to convince an entire culture and society to cultivate a new kind of man and mode of life (as the Nazis were also trying to do)? Has not the fact that he had no normative ethics, nor normative politics, facilitated his criminal misappropriation? Should we not consider his attempt to overthrow the values of the Enlightenment and eradicate the foundations of Christian morality an extremely dangerous maneuver, especially when he could clearly hear the loud strains of Wagnerian music and the nationalism of Bayreuth, which for many philosophers and historians already seems like a prefiguration of Nazism (see Yovel’s essay in this volume)? Brinker and others in this book think that Nietzsche did have some responsibility for Nazi crimes–an argument that has also been made by Steven Aschheim in his study of the Nietzschean legacy in Germany. Many others, including both editors of this volume, think differently.

To tackle this question as soberly and objectively as possible requires going beyond a common defense of Nietzsche in the postwar scholarship. Walter Kaufmann and others were trying to sever Nietzsche altogether from Nazi ideology by stressing the fact that he was fundamentally an apolitical thinker who rejected pan-Germanism and antiSemitism. But it does not necessarily follow that since Nietzsche detested German and other nationalistic attitudes, his teaching was essentially a nonpolitical one. Tempting as it may be to cleanse his thought from the taint of any political ideology, especially that of fascism, it is in fact a misguided strategy. For it is precisely by emphasizing the political import and content of Nietzsche’s philosophy that one can put into a sharper relief his “antifascist” orientation.

The argument that presented Nietzsche as a staunch opponent of the nation-state was especially prevalent among his advocates during the first twenty years after the second World War. They wished to rehabilitate his reputation by denying any trace of resemblance between his writings and those who did almost everything to make them sound compatible with Mein Kampf. As a result, these apologists performed a sweeping depoliticization of Nietzsche’s thought.6 One of the most influential of these commentators was the previously mentioned Walter Kaufmann. Against the generalizing accusations of Crane Brinton (1940, 1941) and others, that Nietzsche was the godfather of Nazism, Kaufmann presented the leitmotif of Nietzsche’s life and thought as that of “the antipolitical individual who seeks self-perfection far from the modern world.”7

It is noteworthy that much contemporary research–which has been less vulnerable to the atmosphere of suspicion that loomed over Nietzsche by the end of the Second World War–tended instead to emphasize the significance of politics in his philosophy. Such scholars sensibly conceded that even if one cannot find in Nietzsche’s antisystematic writings any definite political thought, his radical discussions of morality and concept of the “modern man” had a far reaching political significance. It was within a definite cultural and political context that Nietzsche sought to attain his ideal of a unique and authentic individual cultivating Dionysian values.8

Nietzsche did, however, reject the view that one can justify or rationally derive a political order from certain universalistic principles. It is also true that during his life Nietzsche did not publish anything comparable to Spinoza’s Tractatus Politicus, which was specifically dedicated to political issues. Of course, there were always political implications in writings like his Genealogy of Morals, which critically examined the moral values prevalent in modern society. Moreover, there was an early unpublished composition by Nietzsche (from 1872) that analyses the “Greek state,” and we also have many long passages from his published works that squarely deal with politics.9 We should not forget also that the last sentence Nietzsche had a chance to write before his final collapse did have a pronounced political connotation: Wilhelm, Bismarck und alle Antisemiten abgeschafft (“Wilhelm, Bismarck and all antiSemites abolished”).

It is worthwhile in this context to examine more closely Nietzsche’s so-called confession that he was the “last antipolitical German”. The German equivalent to this term is antipolitisch which is different from unpolitisch–referring to somebody who is utterly indifferent to politics. Indeed Nietzsche, in his Twilight of the Idols, in a section entitled “What the Germans Lack,” distinguished between both of these attitudes to politics by contrasting the Bismarckian modern Reich that embodies a strong political power (Grossmacht) to a society that is essentially antipolitisch. The latter is a social framework that objects to using political force (Kraft) to promote its culture (and Nietzsche in this context gives as an example France, which he calls the “Culturmacht“). None of this made Nietzsche into an antipolitical person, let alone an anarchist. On the contrary, as a great advocate of human creativity, he could see the need for statehood and a civil society in whose framework creativity might take place and flourish. Nietzsche distinguished sharply between the more sublime spiritual and mental powers of individuals (or entire peoples) who generate and produce sublime cultures, and the physical or political force that found expression in overpowering Kraft or Gewalt. Possibly because Hegel, whom Nietzsche criticized in his writings, regarded the Prussian state of the nineteenth century as the highest rational manifestation of the Universal Geist, Nietzsche felt particularly driven to attack this idea of statehood that had attracted his contemporaries. In any case, it is noteworthy that Nietzsche wished his publisher to remove the passage from his Ecce Homo where he supposedly declared himself to be a nonpolitical thinker.

In this passage, Nietzsche actually tries to distance himself not from politics as such (a move that would indeed have made him a nonpolitical thinker) but from the nationalist German politics which at that time raised its ugly head to the ominous tunes of “Deutschland, Deutschland über Alles.” With this militaristic slogan, Nietzsche observes, came “the end of German philosophy.” Thus his statement that he was the “last antipolitical German” could itself be seen as a political statement that strove to overcome nationalism and racism–the “anticultural sickness par excellence.” At any rate, in that passage which, as mentioned above, was not intended for publication, Nietzsche states that due to him being “the last antipolitical German” he is “perhaps more German than present-day Germans, mere citizens of the German Reich, could possibly be.” Nietzsche thereby admits to belonging to the German nation but clearly distances himself (at least in his main compositions during the middle period of his career) from the German Reich of Bismarck. One could almost say that Nietzsche was an antipolitical thinker for political reasons and a political thinker for philosophical reasons, among them his attempt to foster the existential ideal of personal authenticity. In other words, Nietzsche had adopted an antipolitical attitude for reasons that had to do with the future of human culture, an issue which he called “grosse Politik.” For Nietzsche, politics becomes “grand” when it sustains and assists in cultivating human greatness and cultural grandeur. This “great politics” is fundamentally a politics of culture. And if we broadly define politics as an organized and orchestrated mobilization of human resources for the sake of a group or nation, Nietzsche, was indeed deeply engrossed with a politics that would embark on the cultural engineering of the entire society. We ought also to recall that Nietzsche saw in the genuine philosopher the creator of values for future society. Like Plato, Nietzsche envisaged the philosopher as a legislator. Hence Nietzsche is no less political than he is “immoral”–in a very moral and political sense.

Nietzsche abhorred the state only insofar as it became a goal in itself and ceased to function as a means for the advancement and education of autonomous and creative human beings. His preferred and most admired models to achieve the latter ideal were the Greek polis, the virtu of ancient Rome, and the worldly individualism of the Italian Renaissance–cultural patterns that had never made national supremacy the cornerstone of their ideal or regarded the ethnic attributes of their citizens as a mark of creativity or superiority. But there was nothing in his writings to suggest that Nietzsche objected in principle to “the political organization” of statehood as long as it did not become a Leviathan repressing genuine culture and persons.

Nietzsche did not reject the state where it was conducive to authentic life aspirations–a vital element in his philosophy. But once this legitimate (and “natural”) creation changed its nature and became a manifestation of extreme nationalism that hindered free and spontaneous creativity, Nietzsche vehemently opposed it and wished to curb its destructive effects. Perhaps under the influence of Hobbes, Nietzsche would call this kind of state “the coldest of all cold monsters.”10 However, where it encouraged individuals to shape and form their cultural identity in an authentic way, Nietzsche regarded the state as a “blessed means.”

An illuminating case in point is Nietzsche’s attitude toward the aspirations of the Jewish people to establish an independent state for themselves.

For Nietzsche, the history of the Jewish people was a great enigma. He was mesmerized by the example of the Jews in the Diaspora and their ability to establish an effective spiritual-cultural kingdom in Europe without any state or territorial basis. Despite their lack of such support and other adverse and taxing conditions, they had manifested a “plentitude of power without equal to which only the nobility had access” (GS, 136). Nietzsche’s reference to the Jews as the most “powerful race,” in spite of their obvious political and physical weakness, clearly showed that there was nothing physical in the sense of brute force (Kraft) in the Nietzschean concept of power (Macht). One might even assert that Nietzsche’s vision of a “new Europe” devoid of national boundaries and united not by a common economic interest and financial policy but by the wish to foster a Dionysian, genuinely creative culture was partially inspired by the example of European Jewry. Moreover, Nietzsche stressed the fact that even in the most adverse circumstances, the Jewish people “have never ceased to believe in their calling to the highest things” (D, 205). This abundance of spiritual power could best function creatively without national institutions. Hence Nietzsche bestowed on them a vital role in the extraterritorial and supranational Europe of the future when their plentiful power will flow “into great spiritual men and works . . . into an eternal blessing for Europe” (ibid.).

Echoing the Old Testament prophecy about Israel’s magnificent future and its spectacular salvation, Nietzsche claimed that the Jews would once again become the “founders and creators of values.” The creation of values is the most significant task in Nietzsche’s philosophy, which always returns to the “transfiguration of values” and the nature of Western culture, in which the Jews are destined to play the major role as well as to serve as catalysts. Nietzsche’s hope of mobilizing European Jewry to assist him in this transfiguration of values is the background for his emotional exclamation: “What a blessing a Jew is among Germans!” Nietzsche speculated in this context about the possible intermarriage of Jews with Germans or with the best “European nobility” for the sake of enriching a renewed European culture. Nietzsche, in this regard, obviously underestimated the strong and persistent reluctance of many Jews to fully assimilate into their Gentile environment. His views on intermarriage may seem especially perplexing in light of his admiration for Jewish “purity of race,” uniqueness, and pride.

Nietzsche’s cosmopolitan notion of “Jewish calling” might also seem to contradict the national aspirations of the emerging Zionist political movement. But a closer look suggests otherwise. There exists a record of Nietzsche’s conversations in the winter of 1883-34 in Nice with Joseph Paneth–an Austrian Jewish intellectual who was also a good friend of Freud. We know that Nietzsche and Paneth discussed the possibility of the revival of Jewish people in Palestine and their “regeneration” there.11 Nietzsche was apparently not at all happy about the prospect that the Jews might estrange themselves from their Jewish tradition and history to become completely assimilated within the European nations, since such “free spirits (freie Geister) detached from anything are dangerous and destructive” (Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche, 486). He added that one should not ignore the “impact of nationality” and, according to Paneth, he was “quite disappointed that I did not wish to hear anything about the restoration of a Palestinian state” (ibid.). It is certainly possible to imagine Nietzsche supporting the idea of a return of the Jews to the land of Israel and statehood, which, especially in the times of the ancient Hebrews–as he had strongly argued–provided the earthly sources for their spiritual power and legacy. This hypothesis is in a sense implied by Nietzsche’s statement that “in the hands of the Jewish priests the great age in the history of Israel became an age of decay; the Exile” (A, 26). Logically, one way out of this state of “decadence” would be the reestablishment of a Jewish state that revived the secular kingdom of the ancient Hebrews in Zion.

Such a development could also serve Nietzsche’s project of European cultural rejuvenation since it would be quite possible to enlist the “new Israel” and its revival for the sake of “new Europe.” Hence Nietzsche did not see any tension or contradiction between his plan for enlisting Jews for the sake of his new Europe and the Zionist program. He had heard about and was quite aware of the Zionist sentiments awakening among the European Jewry in the last years of his lucidity, and had never given any sign of disapproval or indignation as he did so loudly and eloquently against many other nationalist trends and movements of his time, including the cult of Wagner in Bayreuth. On the contrary, he enthusiastically embraced the future prospects (without excluding the national option) of the Jewish people.12

But what of Nietzsche’s famous immoralism and rejection of traditional Judeo-Christian values? What of his Lebensphilosophie and thoughts about regeneration that at times seemed to envisage the “breeding” of a new elite that would eliminate all the decadent elements within European culture? Did the Nazis not draw some inspiration from his shattering of all moral taboos, his radical, experimental style of thinking, and his apocalyptic visions of the future? Certainly, there were National Socialists who tried to integrate Nietzsche into the strait-jacket of their ideology and exploited his dangerous notion of degeneration. But without its biological racism and anti-Semitism, the Nazi worldview had no real cohesion and Nietzsche was as fierce a critic of these aberrations as one can imagine. Moreover, his so-called immoralism, with its questioning of all dogmas and established values, was hardly the basis on which fascist, Nazi, or other totalitarian regimes consolidated their support. On the contrary, such regimes, however radical their intentions, were careful to appeal to conventional morality and nationalist feelings in order to broaden their following, just as they often paid lip service to democratic values in order better to destroy them. Nietzsche’s skeptical outlook, with its love of ambivalence, ambiguity, and paradox, was far removed from such manipulations, which he could only have despised and abhorred. Certainly, Nietzsche was a disturbing thinker whose ideas will always remain open to a diversity of interpretations. He was no admirer of modernity or of the liberal vision of progress, nor was he a “humanist” in the conventional sense of that term. His work lacked a concrete social anchor and his solution to the problem of nihilism led to a cul-de-sac. But to hold Nietzsche responsible, even indirectly, for Auschwitz, is surely to turn things on their head.13 No other thinker of his time saw as deeply into the pathologies of fin de si`ecle German and European culture, or grasped so acutely from within, the sickness at the heart of anti-Semitism in the Christian West. It would be more just to see in Nietzsche a tragic prophet of the spiritual vacuum that gave birth to the totalitarian abysses of the twentieth century. As such he remains profoundly relevant to our own time.

Return to Book Description

File created: 8/7/2007

Questions and comments to: webmaster@pupress.princeton.edu
Princeton University Press

The Cost of Communalism: Individual Autonomy and Growth in Maxine Hong Kingston’s “No Name Woman” and Rigoberta’s “I, Rigoberta Mench”

The Cost of Communalism: Individual Autonomy and Growth

in Maxine Hong Kingston’s No Name Woman and Rigoberta’s I, Rigoberta Mench

        Patricia Hill Collins, in Shifting the Center, articulates that “Without women’s motherwork, communities would not survive, and by definition, women of color themselves would not survive” (643).  According to Collins, this communal project, however, “extracts a high cost for large numbers of women” (643).  The cost, she says, is that “there is loss of individual autonomy and there is submersion of individual growth for the benefit of the group” (643, emphasis added).  Similarly, in Asian and Native American culture, for the benefit of the community, women’s individual autonomy and individual growth are often submersed as well.  Maxine Hong Kingston’s unnamed protagonist, in No Name Woman, and Rigoberta, in I, Rigoberta Mench, both sacrifice their individual autonomies and individual growths for the benefit of their communities.  Their seemingly self-sacrificing ego-dissolutions, however, are not some conscious, individual choice they make; rather, they are unconscious choices owed to their cultural upbringings and the social systems they are born into.  Although, their willingness to lose their egos is highly noble, they are simply abiding by the powerfully effective, unstipulated moral laws operating within their communities for generations. 

For the women of color, more specifically, women of older Chinese generation and Native American women, communalism is not a choice, but a way of life they are born into and must hold on to.  For Rigoberta and Kingston’s unnamed aunt, therefore, individual autonomy and growth are not alternatives they consciously deny.  Both protagonists are oblivious to other ways of living.  To them, communities are the only support system they know.  They believe that a good life is attained only through strict adherence to their ancestral customs.  As an option, if self-autonomy was offered to Rigoberta and the unnamed aunt, they, most likely, would have rejected it for a wise reason.  For any woman, who has never known other culture nor crossed over communal boundaries, to defect her own community would be deemed suicidal and self-destructive.  It can translate to death, if not literally, then psychologically.  It is not surprising, therefore, that regardless of the severe hardships Rigoberta and the unnamed aunt encounter, they do not think to venture out of their communal boundaries; for them, communalism is not only the safest but the only way of life.   

Due to social and cultural conditioning, the sense of communal identity for Rigoberta and the unnamed aunt eclipses their sense of self identity.  In Rigoberta’s case, her communal identity starts to formulate while she is yet in her mother’s womb.  When her parents make the birth announcement to the people in their community, she becomes their collective asset because her parents promise the people that her baby “belong to the community and [that the baby] would…serve it when [he/she] grew up” (49).  In Rigoberta’s Indian culture, even the personhood is a communal asset – every person is owned and shared by one another.  On her tenth birthday, her communal identity is further reinforced.  According to her Indian traditions, she makes an oral, yet official promise to her community that she will “do many things for the [them]” (49).  Her parents make sure that she repeats the vow in front of every single person in the community.  Corollary to such cultural and social inculcations, Rigoberta grows up with a peculiar sensibility and conscience; she feels and thinks of her community before she does her selfhood.  Likewise, the fact that Kingston’s unnamed aunt, wields no significant, individual power over her life, casts her as someone lacking self identity.  Kingston articulates that Chinese, patriarchal culture and customs are responsible for her aunt’s lack of individuality.  According to Kingston, “women in the old China” (310), would naturally be more community conscious than self conscious, because her life is controlled by forces other than herself (emphasis added).  For instance, she “did not [have the right to] choose” (310), “not even the biggest event of one’s life – marriage” (310).  Kingston continues to speak for her aunt:  “When the family found a young man in the next village to be her husband, she…promised before they met that she would be his forever” (310).  In other words, her aunt’s course of life was dictated more by community customs than her individual will, thus weakening her selfhood.  Her life is owned by patriarchal authorities and maneuvered by communal customs.  Psychologically and socially, she is so repressed that she has no room to forge an identity of her own.  Thus for both Rigoberta and the unnamed aunt, the fact that their communal identities are more dominant over their individual identities is a result of social/cultural construction. 

As in the case of Rigoberta and the unnamed aunt, once their minds are culturally/socially constructed to abide by the communal ideologies, then, any inklings of individuality are deemed eccentric, problematic, and antithesis to communal solidarity.  In other words, individualism and communalism are considered to be mutually exclusive, and thus cannot coexist in one person’s mind.  In the minds of Rigoberta and the unnamed aunt, the collective, communal identities are so deeply ingrained that a concept of individual pursuit and growth is almost non-existent.  If they have any sense of self-identity, then, it is sure to be culturally suppressed and submersed, until they no longer crave it nor recognize it.  These two women’s main preoccupations and anxieties deal only with issues concerning communal values and their personal conformity to them.  Rigoberta’s elder sister echoes this notion of cultural conformity when she tells Rigoberta to “accept life as it is” (49).  Her sister exhorts Rigoberta that “[they] shouldn’t become bitter or look for diversions or escape outside the laws of [their] parents,” (49).  Likewise, according to Kingston’s mother, back in her (and the unnamed aunt’s) Chinese hometown, not only every woman in the village shared a common will, they even looked alike: “All the married women blunt-cut their hair in flaps about their ears or pulled it back in tight buns.  No nonsense” (311), she say.  In fact, Kingston’s mother continues, “a woman who tended her appearance reaped a reputation for eccentricity” (311).  Thus, for Asians and Native Americans, then, apparently, the community’s ultimate goal is that everyone blends well with the whole; no one should stand out; everyone should merge harmoniously with one another.  Under this politic of communal solidarity, individual egos must be sacrificed to sustain this utopian ideology of “oneness.”  

Interestingly, in a well-ordered community, there are unstipulated, moral laws which heightens this oneness in a perverse way because if any one member violates the law, then, that person becomes the common enemy of the entire community and receives severe punishments.  Rigoberta says that in her community, their common “enemy is someone who steals or goes into prostitution” (57).  She says that in her community, laws are formulated orally: “this is how we make our pleas and…promises” (57).  Although Rigoberta realizes that her law making customs “[do not] reflect so much to the real world” (57), she asserts that this is “[her people’s] reality” (57).  Furthermore, if a member of Rigoberta’s community endangers the lives of other members, “although it hurts us,” she says, the people “would have to execute [that person]” (146).  Likewise, in the unnamed aunt’s village, there are unwritten moral laws, too, that are more powerful and effective than any written state laws.  If in Rigoberta’s village, a prostitute is the villager’s common enemy, in the village of the unnamed aunt, an adulterer is.  Kingston tells us that her aunt became the villager’s common enemy because the people believed “that her [aunt’s] infidelity had…harmed the village” (313).  The villagers demanded that she tell the name of the impregnator, but her aunt did not disclose it, thereby paying the ultimate price of being private, for keeping “the man’s name to herself ” (312, emphasis added).  Kingston confirms that the ultimate reason why “the villagers punished her [aunt],” (313) was because she “act[ed] as if she could have a private life, secret and apart from them” (313, emphasis added).  The villagers “ripped up her clothes and shoes and broke her combs, grinding them underfoot…‘Pig.’ ‘Ghost.’ ‘Pig.’” (309).  After the villagers left, however, her own family members exacerbate her misery.  They relentlessly rebuke her, too, for being an unfit, dishonorable member of their family who has acted singularly in an infamous way: “the family broke their silence and cursed her…Death is coming. Death is coming.  Look what you’ve done.  You’ve killed us. Ghost! Dead ghost! Ghost! You’ve never been born” (314).  Her family, unable to accept her disgraceful eccentricity, disowns her, and her place in the community thus altogether disappears.  Although she is not what Rigoberta describes as someone “guilty of endangering a member of community,” she, with her newborn infant, self-executes both lives by drowning in a well.  Thus, in such a tightly-knitted community where “all [in] the village were kinsmen” (313), those who become the common enemy of the villagers by breaking the communal law, can/will suffer ignominious punishment.  The unnamed aunt literally, and perhaps heroically, loses her ego to soothe the villager’s collective shame, superstitious fear, and indignity.

If the unnamed aunt’s death is a literal dissolution of self in an attempt to lift her sexual curse from the village people, Rigoberta’s self-sacrificing decision to not marry is also a form of mental, self-dissolution for the sake of her community.  Rigoberta genuinely feels that any form of individual growth and autonomy, namely, even marriage on her part, is a selfish act that betrays the communal vows she made as a girl.  As a female bound by such communal vows, however, she admits that she, too, had her share of struggles and temptations in terms of personal aspirations:   

As I said, I was engaged once…I came to all sorts of conclusions because I loved this companero…Well, there I was between these two things – choosing him or my people’s struggle.  And [community] that’s what I chose, and I left my companero with much sadness and heavy heart.  But I told myself that I had a lot to do for my people and I didn’t need a pretty house while they lived in horrific conditions. (225-6)

Seemingly from pure altruism, Rigoberta devotes everything she has/is for the cause of her beloved community.  Her message is unequivocal: “my primary duty is to my people and then to my personal happiness” (225).  It is clear that Rigoberta’s individual autonomy and growth are the dear price she willingly pays to live up to her communal expectations.

The stories of both I, Rigoberta Menchu and No Name Woman illustrate that a woman born into a communalistic social structure has no room for individualism.  One of the key concepts of communalism is that each member in the community is inextricably weaved into the whole, as one big family.  Every one thus share one, all-inclusive identity that eclipse any individual identities.  Both the unnamed aunt and Rigoberta, mentally and literally, dissolve their sense of selves into the larger, utopian “us” concept for the sake of their communities.  Also, what these two stories have in common, is that in a sound communal system, there are unstipulated laws – though not written – govern its members more powerfully, effecting the choices and shaping the conducts of its members.  As Rigoberta’s thoughtful responses to individual autonomy and growth reveals, women who are ingrained into communal ideologies and committed to communal solidarities will willingly give up their egos and autonomies for the sake of the collective, communal good.

Works Cited

Collins, Patricia Hill. “Shifting the Center: Race, Class, and Feminist Theorizing About Motherhood.” The Longman Anthology of Women’s Literature. 

DeShazer, Mary K.  New York: Addison-Wesley Educational, 2001. 638-653.

Kingston, Maxine Hong. “No Name Woman.” The Longman Anthology of Women’s Literature.  DeShazer, Mary K.  New York: Addison-Wesley Educational, 2001. 308-315.

Menchu, Rigoberta. I, Rigoberta Menchu. Wright, Ann. New York: Verso, 1984.

The Galvanized Victim Reciprocates Abuse to the Electro-perpetrator

The Galvanized Victim Reciprocates Abuse to the Electro-perpetrator

 Death and the Maiden is a play written by Ariel Dorfman after seven years of exile from Chile when General Augusto Pinochet was still the dictator of the nation.  In this play, Dorfman explores the unstable psyche of citizens of Chile who had undergone horrific abuse by the Pinochet’s regime.  Dorfman uses his protagonist, Paulina, as an emblem that embodies the citizens of Chile who have been victimized by fascism.  In the play, Paulina is raped and abused under the high-voltage, electric currents by the secret servicemen of the Pinochet’s regime.  Paulina’s physical and psychological wounds from this abuse symbolically represent the scars of Chileans who had been victimized by fascism.  Electricity that is used by the secret serviceman is also an emblem that signifies the annihilative power of fascism.  Dorfman’s use of electricity as a metaphor warns that if the power of government is not monitored with moral conscience, it can bring devastating, irreparable outcomes, not only to its oppressed citizens, but also to the regime itself.  In Ariel Dorfman’s Death and the Maiden, Dr. Roberto is the secret serviceman of fascism who rapes and galvanizes Paulina, a woman who represents the victimized citizens of Chile.  Due to Roberto’s abusive use of high-voltage electricity, Paulina, ironically, transmogrifies into a perpetrator who “reciprocates” the same level of abuse back to Roberto, resulting in a reversal of role and power between the two parties, symbolically dismantling fascism. 

In order to understand how the power of electricity signifies fascism in Dorfman’s play, first, it is helpful to examine the nature and the power of electricity.  Electricity has both regenerative and annihilative powers.  Its regenerative power is seen in all living organisms, from the photosynthesis of plants to the radiation therapy of humans (that uses X-rays or ultraviolet light to heal and lengthen human life).  In Dorfman’s play, however, the regenerative power of electricity signifies the freedom and democracy that would enhance the lives of Chileans.  Electricity’s annihilative power is just as actively sought after by humans; for example, radiation injury (ionizing radiation) that causes sickness to nuclear energy (radioactive energy from fission) that causes widespread destruction of life and the environment.  Metaphorically, electricity’s annihilative power in Dorfman’s play alludes to fascism that kills individualism and free society.  Electricity, therefore, can either electrocute (kill) or electrify (revive); for this reason, its power must be governed with ethical prudence.

Because electricity has power to kill, the danger of mishandling its power escalates in the hands of the brutal perpetrator like Roberto, who is morbidly curious and devoid of ethics.  Roberto, in Death and the Maiden, confesses his perverse curiosity in electrically-induced, human anatomy: “My curiosity was partly morbid, partly scientific.  How much can this woman take?…Does her sex dry up when you put the current through her?  Can she have an orgasm under those circumstances?” (59).  Under Fascism, the victims who fall under such inhumane Doctor, at best, are severely abused, and at worst, face possible death: “She is entirely in your power, you can carry out all your fantasies, you can do what you want with her” (59).  Thus, the brutality of Dr. Roberto reveals how electricity (the power of fascism) in the hands of the few powerful can injure its laboratory victims (its citizens).  By emblematizing electricity as a metaphor, Dorfman indirectly and artfully demonstrates the perverse and brutal power of fascism under Pinochet.

Surely, the rape and the electro-abuse that Roberto commit against Paulina are bizarre and inhumane, potentially producing psychological electrogenetic symptoms in her.  For instance, Paulina avoids light, so much so that her husband, Geraldo, constantly adds more light into their inhabitant.  In the dark of the night, Geraldo comes home to his wife, Paulina, and finds her “hidden behind the curtains.  He switches on a light” (3).  Geraldo, again, adds more light to find his dinner: “He puts on another lamp and sees the table set” (4).  Furthermore, the scene in which Roberto visits Geraldo reveals that Paulina instinctively pushes Roberto away from her presence by turning off the light: “Someone knocks…A lamp is switched on…[but] is immediately switched off” (12).  Paulina’s aberrant behavior towards “light” seems to suggest that these symptoms link to the high voltage, electro-shocks she suffered.  Symbolically, it is a post-fascist, psychological symptoms marked in the citizens of Chile.  Her symptoms allude to the mistrusting and fearful mentality of Chileans in the aftermath of Pinochet’s regime.  The citizens rather find refuge in the dark, for they fear that the electric lights, which represent the power of fascism, might rape them once more, pulverizing their individual dignity.

In addition to Paulina’s deliberate avoidance of lights, she also exhibits behaviors that seem to evince that she has been desensitized to violence by the electric stimuli.  First, the biological impact of electric stimuli on Paulina’s body can be examined to analogically link her symptoms to that of the citizens of Chile.  According to Siniaia, a neurologist, “in mammalian,…central nervous systems exhibit habituation and/or sensitization of their responses to repetitive stimuli” (Siniaia, 1).  In other words, “electric stimulation of infralimbic subregion (lower area of cerebrum) reduces conditioned…fear stimuli” (Milad 1).  These scientific studies cast light on why, perhaps, Paulina in the play exhibits no fear.  Also this impact of electric stimulations on mammalian is analogous to the fascist regime that not only repeatedly manipulates and controls the minds of its citizens, but also desensitizes the citizens to violence.  Paulina, who had undergone near-death experience with electric shocks, shows no fear of abusing or killing her perpetrator, Roberto: “When I heard his voice, I thought the only thing I want is to have him raped” (40).  She continues: “What do we lose by killing one of them?” (66)    Roberto’s electro-abuse against Paulina that symbolizes fascist brutality, in effect, has desensitized and galvanized her into a perpetrator.  Thus, the electrically desensitized Paulina symbolizes Chileans who are apathetic to the violence and death after many years of repetitive, brutal stimulations from the Pinochet’s regime.

Just as the studies on electric stimulations give insights into that Paulina could have been desensitized to violence, examining other characteristics of electricity provide cues to the victim’s reciprocal behaviors.  Scientifically, Paulina’s act of reciprocating abuse back to Roberto can be analyzed, hypothetically, that the victim’s “impedance” (Giaever 2) is at action, an electro-phenomenon that is defined as an overall opposition to electric currents.  In other words, human bodies, innately, either neutralize or resist electric stimuli off their bodies.  This tendency of human bodies can be analogically adapted to assume that oppressed Chileans will naturally find ways to either neutralize or fight fascism off their state.  Furthermore, electricity is not static; it is intrinsically mobile, an electro-phenomenon termed as “electromotion.”  Electricity – either negatively/positively charged – naturally travels from one place/thing to another, transmitting its energy on to that which it comes in contact with.  In order to apply this intrinsic nature of electricity to human phenomena, this mobility of electricity can be figuratively adapted as “violence begets violence.”  In other words, electricity’s inherent mobility can be reinterpreted metaphorically to explicate why Roberto’s electro-abuse would affect Paulina, and her galvanized energy, in turn, would haunt him.  Thus, from electromotive phenomena, a simile can be drawn to hypothesize human phenomena: that one person’s negative/positive motives engender another’s negative/positive motives accordingly.  Whether the interpretation is scientific or metaphoric, one, coterminous analysis can be derived from this electromotive hypothesis: humans, in general, are innately born with reciprocal impulses to, at least, oppose or resist negative energy, if not to reciprocate exactly, as ill for ill and good for good.  Thus, symbolically, the violence suffered by the Chileans under Pinochet’s fascism has natural tendencies to be reciprocated by the victims unto the perpetrators.

This metaphoric interpretation of electromotion – the galvanic mobility plus its tendency to reciprocate – can be divided into two major, insurgent movements to analyze Paulina’s act of revenge.  The first movement is Paulina’s character metamorphosis, her character transformation into that of her perpetrator, Roberto.  This character transformation prepares and enables her to reciprocate abuse.  The second movement of insurgence is the consummation of revenge, the actual act of reciprocating abuse for abuse and violence for violence, ultimately undermining the authority of Roberto. 

The first movement of insurgence – the victim’s character metamorphosis – primarily comes through “character mimesis,” meaning that Paulina transforms into a perpetrator through mimicry, ultimately mirroring Roberto’s demeanor and gender.  For instance, Paulina mimics male’s voice and demeanor: “She…discovers Roberto about to free himself…Paulina ties him up again, while her voice assumes male tones” (37).  She, in effect, is transforming herself into an assertive and preemptive fascist.  She no longer wants to be the submissive citizen anymore.  In fact, she regrets that in “All [her] life, [she’s] always been much too obedient” (58).  Paulina is no longer reactive, nor heeds to fascist authority.  The following passage shows that she is now a different citizen; she appropriates fascist authority: “I don’t need to ask him…I gave him the name Bud, Doctor…I inserted in my story to Gerardo, and you corrected most of them.  It turned out just as I planned…I’m going to kill you because you’re guilty” (64-5).  Paulina’s character transformation represents Chileans who are preparing to take actions into their own hands, transmogrifying into the very same demeanor of their fascist perpetrators.

The final movement of insurgence – the consummation of revenge – reaches its climax as Paulina not only gains full control of her perpetrator, but also dismantles his power and authority that which represents fascism.  Paulina triumphs when Roberto, after many hours of psychological and physical abuse, begs her for a pardon.  “Forgiveness” (60), Roberto cries out, and “writes down” (61) his confession while Paulina “hear [his vocal] confession on the tape” (61).  Roberto even “gets down on his knees” (65); his once-powerful, fascist authority totally dismantles.  The only thing that stops Paulina from actually killing Roberto is that her abuse from him, however brutal, does not add up to a murder: “Kill them? Kill him?  As he didn’t kill me, I think it wouldn’t be fair to –” (34). Paulina knows that because Roberto represents only an administrator of fascism, killing him would not kill the entire system.  In fact, what she really wants is for him to confess, repent and reform.  In other words, what the people of Chile want from their previous regime is that it admits its brutality and compensates for it.  In this last scene of the play, since Roberto has confessed and repented, Paulina and the people of Chile is satisfied and show that their insurgence have successfully culminated to the full cycle of reciprocity.

Paulina’s successful act of dismantling the authority and power of Roberto attests to the reversal of power between the two parties.  The fact that Dorfman has chosen a woman as a victim, and not a man, dramatizes the uneven power relations between Pinochet’s regime and Chileans.  Moreover, by emblematizing an element that is as prodigious, yet destructive, as electricity, Dorfman poignantly stresses the brutality of Pinochet’s fascism.  However, the fact that his protagonist, Paulina, does not kill Roberto at the end of the play shows that the author advocates peace between the perpetrators and the victims who have survived Pinochet’s fascism.  Thus, the prime purpose of Dorfman’s play, The Death and The Maiden, is not to provoke anger, but to provide a purging effect in the Chilean audience.  In other words, the fact that Paulina – who represents the victims of Chile – wields her power to successfully flip the power relations with that of Roberto allows the Chilean audience to vicariously channel out their decades-old, fascist toxics, and thus become relieved and free.

 

Works Cited

Dorfman, Ariel. Death and the Maiden. New York: Penguin, 1991.

Giaever, Ivar, et al., eds. “Electrical Wound-Healing Assay for Cells in Vitro.”  PNAS

101.6 (2004): 1554-1559.

Milad, M.R. et al., eds. “Electrical Stimulation of Medial Prefrontal Cortex Reduces

Conditioned Fear in a Temporally Specific Manner.” Behavioral Neuroscience

118.2 (2004): 389-394.

Siniaia M.S., et al., eds. “Habituation and desensitization of the Hering-Breuer Reflex in

        Rat.” The Journal of Physiology: 523.2 (2000): 479-91.

Comparative Analysis on Ariel Dorfman’s “Death and the Maiden” and Mary Shelley’s “Frankenstein”

                The Galvanized Victims Reciprocate Abuse to the Electroscientists

    In the 19th century, Thomas Edison laid the basis for the technological and social revolution of the modern electric world.  Today, electricity has become one of the core elements of human civilization.  Its study and experimentations, however, if not monitored with moral conscience, can bring devastating, irreparable outcomes, not only to the experimentees, but also to the experimenters.  In Ariel Dorfman’s Death and the Maiden and Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein, the two scientists, Roberto and Victor, both conduct inhumane and bizarre experiments that involve electricity on human anatomy.  Their electrological assays, however, due to their abusive use of high-voltage electricity, produce reciprocal behavior in the laboratory victims that stem from the two central characteristics of electricity: the “electrogenesis” (the effects of electric stimulus on organisms) and the “electromotion” (the mobility of galvanic currents).  The synergy of these two electrodynamics transmogrify the victims into perpetrators who “reciprocate” the same level of abuse back to the scientists – metaphorically and literally, resulting in a reversal of role and power between the two parties.  Thus, the electricized Paulina reciprocates by assuming the role of a patriarch, undermining the authority and power of Roberto; likewise, the electrically vivified monster reciprocates by presuming the master’s role, ultimately dismantling the authority and power of Victor.

In order to understand how electric stimulations affect the two protagonists, Paulina and the monster, first, the nature and the power of electricity need to be examined.  Electricity has both regenerative and annihilative powers.  Its regenerative power is seen in all living organisms, from the photosynthesis of plants to the radiation therapy of humans (that uses X-rays or ultraviolet light to heal and lengthen human life).  Today, in fact, electricity is an inextricable component in most of the scientific assays, whether it is to eradicate bacteria, germs, or cancerous cells, or to revive, lengthen, and enhance the lives of various organisms.  Electricity’s annihilative power, however, is just as actively sought after by humans: for example, radiation injury (ionizing radiation) that causes sickness to nuclear energy (radioactive energy from fission) that causes widespread destruction of life and the environment.  Fifteen-year-old Victor witnesses the electro-annihilation of a tree firsthand: “[It was] a most violent and terrible thunder-storm…I beheld a stream of fire issue from an old and beautiful oak…and as soon as the dazzling light vanished, the oak had disappeared” (25, emphasis added).  He inquires of his father what that fire or light was, and his “[father] replies, ‘Electricity’”(26, emphasis added).  The power of electricity, just as Victor had witnessed, has the power to kill and obliterate.  Electricity, therefore, can either electrocute (kill) or electrify (revive) organisms; for this reason, the electrological experiments must be conducted with ethical prudence.

Because electricity has power to kill, the danger of mishandling its power escalates in the hands of the perverse and brutal scientists like Roberto and Victor, who are morbidly curious and devoid of ethics.  Roberto, in Death and the Maiden, confesses his perverse curiosity in electro-stimulated, human anatomy: “My curiosity was partly morbid, partly scientific.  How much can this woman take?…Does her sex dry up when you put the current through her?  Can she have an orgasm under those circumstances?” (59).  The victims who fall under such perverse scientists, at best, are severely abused, and at worst, face possible death: “She is entirely in your power, you can carry out all your fantasies, you can do what you want with her” (59).  Victor in Frankenstein is just as perverse and dangerous in his scientific imagination: “Life and death appeared to me ideal bounds, which I should first break through, and pour a torrent of light into our dark world” (37).  According to Peterfreund, Victor’s phrase “pour a torrent of light” was conceived in the late eighteenth century as an “electricity fluid,…‘infusing life into an inanimate’ – that is, an unmoving – ‘body,’ a matter pouring electrical fluid into it” (Peterfreund 5).  Victor further confesses that his morbid violence increases as his perverse curiosity – “infusing life into an inanimate” (Peterfreund 5) – increases: “I dabbled among the unhallowed damps of the grave, or tortured the living animal to animate the lifeless clay…and almost frantic impulse, urged me forward; I seemed to have lost all soul or sensation but for this one pursuit” (38).  This passage shows that Victor had succumbed to the dangerous, potentially annihilating “enticements of science” (34).  The monster curses Victor’s “enticements of science” (34) as unhallowed curiosity: “I shall collect my funeral pile, and consume to ashes this miserable frame, that its remains may afford no light to any curious and unhallowed wretch, who would create such another as I have been” (191, emphasis added).  Thus, the monster’s curse suggests that none but those who have prudence and ethics should have the access to this prodigious, yet destructive, power of electricity.

Surely, the ethicality of scientific methods convicts Roberto and Victor’s electrological experiments as inhumane, abusive, and potentially producing psychological electrogenetic symptoms in the victims.  For instance, Paulina avoids light, so much so that her husband, Geraldo, constantly adds more light in their habitation.  In the dark of the night, Geraldo comes home to his wife, Paulina, and finds her “hidden behind the curtains.  He switches on a light” (3).  Geraldo, again, adds more light to find his dinner: “He puts on another lamp and sees the table set” (4).  Furthermore, the scene in which Roberto visits Geraldo reveals that between the two dwellers – Geraldo and Paulina – there are conflicting behavioral patterns towards light: “Someone knocks…A lamp is switched on…[but] is immediately switched off…Gerardo switches on the lamp” (12) again.  Whereas Paulina psychologically and physically withdraws from the light and finds security in the dark, the monster, in contrast, acts hysterical to light, more specifically, to fire: “I placed a variety of combustibles around the cottage… As the night advanced, a fierce wind arose…and produced a kind of insanity in my spirits, that burst all bounds of reason and reflection…with a loud scream, I fired…The wind fanned the fire, and the cottage was quickly enveloped by the flames” (116, emphasis added).  Furthermore, it is significant to note that the first word the monster ever learns is, strangely, “fire”: “I learned and applied the words fire, milk, bread, and word” (93, emphasis in original).  The monster’s hysterical and mystical ties to “fire” and Paulina’s aberrant behavior towards “light” seem to suggest that these symptoms link to the high voltage, electro-shocks they suffered – the psychological electrogenetic effect. 

While the victims’ abnormal behaviors in immediate contact with the light or fire can be regarded as psychological electrogenetic symptoms, there are other signs in the victims that are neurological in origin.  Modern science illuminate that electric stimuli not only manipulate the minds of the experimentees, but also desensitize their fear stimuli.  In 2003, Berg R.W. and Kleinfeld D. from UCSD Department of Physics have conducted a study of rhythmic, motor activity of the vibrissae (whisk) to understand the patterned, motor activity in mammals (Berg 1).  Evidence suggests that “neural circuitry in the brain provides rhythmic drive to the vibrissae” (Berg 1).  In other words, electric stimuli alter the minds of the animals, engendering involuntary muscular motions that they have no control over.  More significantly, scientists have discovered that “in mammalian…central nervous systems exhibit habituation and/or sensitization of their responses to repetitive [electric] stimuli” (Siniaia, 1).  In other words, “electric stimulation of infralimbic subregion (lower area of cerebrum) reduces conditioned…fear stimuli” (Milad 1).  These neurological electrogenetic findings provide cues to why, perhaps, as the monster informs Victor – the electroscientist who has severely galvanized him – that he no longer has fearful senses: “you, my tyrant and tormentor…[b]eware; for I am fearless, and therefore powerful” (144).  The monster is so desensitized and thus fearless that he even plans to end his own life by the flames: “I shall ascend my funeral pile triumphantly, and exult in the agony of the torturing flames” (191, emphasis added).  Likewise, Paulina, who had undergone near-death experience with electro-abuses, shows no fear of abusing or killing her perpetrator, Roberto: “When I heard his voice, I thought the only thing I want is to have him raped” (40).  She continues: “What do we lose by killing one of them?” (66)  The only thing that stops her from actually killing Roberto is that her abuse from him, however brutal, does not add up to a murder: “Kill them? Kill him?  As he didn’t kill me, I think it wouldn’t be fair to –” (34).  Thus, the electrically desensitized Paulina and the monster seem to exhibit neurological electrogenetic symptoms – no fear to violence or death.

While psychological and neurological electrogenetic symptoms in the victims are more visible and external, their internal electrogenetic wounds, however, are much less legible.  For instance, Paulina’s electrogenetic conditions, though real, are only visible to her husband who lives with her: “If I were to accept, I must know I can count on you, that you don’t feel…if you were to have a relapse” (9) – Geraldo worries.  He deals with Paulina’s electrogenetic conditions on a daily basis, but it is hidden, rather, invisible to others: “Nobody knows.  Not even your mother knows” (9).  The modern day science, however, detects electrogenetic conditions at cellular levels, and thus sheds insight into symptoms that are like that of Paulina’s or the monster’s.  The following medical studies by American and German scientists illuminate that even a very small amount of electricity can have a devastating, physiological impact on organisms: “The fate of the killed cells shows that for electroporation [or wounding], the duration is generally a few hundred milliseconds;…up to tens of seconds result in cell killing” (Giaever, 3).  If only a few, hundred milliseconds of low voltage, electro-shocks can seriously wound and tens of seconds kill cultured cells, then, it is scientifically feasible to diagnose that Paulina, as well as the monster, being gone through such high-voltage electro-shocks, carry wounded, altered, or dead cells in their bodies, thus having internal, invisible electrogenetic scars. 

If psychological, neurological, and internal electrogenetic symptoms in the galvanized victims are scientifically feasible, the “electromotion,” however, although scientifically sound, can not convey human behaviors.  Therefore, to interpret literature, especially to better understand why the victims reciprocate abuse back to the perpetrators, the term “electromotion,” in addition to its scientific meaning, should be reinterpreted metaphorically.  First, if electromotion is scientifically applied, then, the reciprocal impulse in the victims can be analyzed as, hypothetically, that the victim’s “impedance” is at action, an electro-phenomenon that is defined as an overall opposition to electric currents (Giaever 2).  In other words, the various organisms, innately, either neutralize or resist electric stimuli off their bodies.  Secondly, electricity is intrinsically mobile, not static.  Electricity – either negatively/positively charged – naturally travels from one place/thing to another, transmitting its energy on to that which it comes in contact with.  In order to apply this intrinsic nature of electricity to human phenomena, this mobility of electricity can be figuratively adapted as “violence begets violence.”  In other words, the electromotion – the galvanic mobility – can be reinterpreted metaphorically to explicate why Roberto and Victor’s electro-abuses would affect Paulina and the monster, and why Paulina and the monster’s galvanized energies, in turn, would haunt Roberto and Victor respectively.  Thus, from electromotive phenomena, a simile can be drawn to theorize human phenomena: that one’s negative/positive motives engender another’s negative/positive motives accordingly.  Whether the interpretation is scientific or metaphoric, one, coterminous analysis can be derived from this electromotive hypothesis: humans, in general, innately have the reciprocal impulses to, at least, oppose or resist negative energy, if not to reciprocate exactly, as ill for ill and good for good.  Thus, analogically, it is only natural that Paulina and the monster will reciprocate the same level of abuse back to Roberto and Victor respectively. 

This analogical interpretation of electromotion – the galvanic mobility as representing the victim’s tendency to reciprocate – can be divided into two successive, insurgent movements to analyze Paulina’s and the monster’s acts of revenge.  The first movement of insurgence is the victim’s character metamorphosis – the victim’s character transformation into that of the perpetrator – which prepares and enables them to reciprocate abuse.  The second movement of insurgence is the consummation of the revenge, reciprocating abuse for abuse, and violence for violence. 

The first movement of insurgence – the victim’s character metamorphosis – primarily comes through “character mimesis,” meaning that the victims transform into perpetrators through mimicry, ultimately mirroring the perpetrators’ demeanor, class, and gender.  For instance, Paulina mimics male’s voice and demeanor: “She…discovers Roberto about to free himself…Paulina ties him up again, while her voice assumes male tones” (37).  She, in effect, is transmogrifying herself into an assertive and preemptive patriarch.  She no longer wants to be the submissive female anymore.  In fact, she regrets that in “All [her] life, [she’s] always been much too obedient” (58).  Paulina is no longer reactive, nor heeds to male authority.  The following passage shows that she is now a different woman – she appropriates male authority: “I don’t need to ask him…I gave him the name Bud, Doctor…I inserted in my story to Gerardo, and you corrected most of them.  It turned out just as I planned…I’m not going to kill you because you’re guilty, Doctor, but because you haven’t repented at all” (64-5).  The monster shows even more of this character mimesis.  He, too, mimics his creator’s high class culture; he learns his master’s language “in close attention, that [he] might more speedily master the language” (98).  His readings, to name a few, include “Paradise Lost, a volume of Plutarch’s Lives, and the Sorrows of Werter” (99).  The monster eventually transforms into a persuasive, authoritative elitist like his creator, so much so that Victor warns Walton of the monster’s eloquence: “He is eloquent and persuasive; and once his words had even power over my heart: but trust him not” (179).  The monster’s impressive linguistic skills resemble the very intelligence, charm, and class of Victor.  In fact, Walton, who later becomes utterly overwhelmed by the monster’s audacity and eloquence, writes to his sister: “Great God! What a scene has just taken place!” (187)  The monster’s demeanor and eloquence that Walton later witnesses evince that he has successfully acculturated into that of the master’s class through mimicry.  Thus, both Paulina and the monster, through character mimesis, transmogrify into perpetrators; and this character transformation enables them to reciprocate abuse – the first movement of insurgence.

The final movement of insurgence – the culmination of reciprocity – reaches its full cycle as Paulina and the monster not only gain full control of their perpetrators, but also dismantle their power and authority.  Paulina triumphs when Roberto, after many hours of psychological and physical abuse, begs her for a pardon.  “Forgiveness” (60), Roberto cries out, and “writes down” (61) his confession while Paulina “hear [his vocal] confession on the tape” (61).  Roberto even “gets down on his knees,” (65) his once-powerful, male authority as a perpetrator totally dismantles.   Likewise, the monster successfully inflicts the same level of, if not an exceeding amount of, pain to Victor.  He kills his best friend, Clerval; his wife, Elizabeth; his brother, William; and frames Justine for William’s murder.  Furthermore, Victor’s father dies from the sorrow, and he himself eventually dies due to the horror and trauma caused by his creature who reciprocates evil to his most beloved, circle of people.  Perhaps, the monster’s most defining moment of victory over his creator is best resonated in the words he utters to Victor in their last encounter: “Slave, I before reasoned with you, but you have proved yourself unworthy of my condescension.  Remember that I have power…You are my creator, but I am your master; — obey!” (144).  The fact that monster overpowers Victor  effectuates a reversal of role between the two party.  Thus, both Paulina and the monster ultimately succeed in dismantling the power and authority of Roberto and Victor respectively, the consummation of reciprocity.

Could the insurgence been prevented by the perpetrators?  Are the electrogenetic symptoms in the victims real?  Are the electromotive forces in the galvanized victims unstoppable?  Either electrically abused or animated, Paulina in Ariel Dorfman’s Death and the Maiden and the monster in Mary Shelley’s Frankenstein both manifest electrogenetic symptoms that are scientifically conceivable.  While the victims’ electrogenetic symptoms can be analyzed scientifically, their reciprocal behaviors, however, can not be explained by science alone.  Therefore, the intrinsic mobility of electricity – the electromotion – is applied metaphorically as “violence begets violence” to explicate why the galvanized victims reciprocate violence to their perpetrators.  Both Dorfman’s play and Shelley’s novel send strong warnings to the readers that mishandling the prodigious, yet destructive, power of electricity can bring irreparable outcomes, not only to the experimentees, but also to the experimenters.

Works Cited

Berg, R. W., and Kleinfeld, D. “Vibrissa Movement Elicited by Rhythmic Electrical

        Microstimulation to Motor Cortex in the Aroused Rat Mimics Exploratory

        Whisking.” Journal of Neurophysiology 90.5 (2003): 2950-63.

Dorfman, Ariel. Death and the Maiden. New York: Penguin, 1991.

Giaever, Ivar, et al., eds. “Electrical Wound-Healing Assay for Cells in Vitro.”  PNAS

101.6 (2004): 1554-1559.

Hustis, Harriet. “Responsible Creativity and the ‘Modernity’ of Mary Shelley’s

        Prometheus.” Studies in English Literature 43 (2003): 845-60.

Milad, M.R. et al., eds. “Electrical Stimulation of Medial Prefrontal Cortex Reduces

Conditioned Fear in a Temporally Specific Manner.” Behavioral Neuroscience

118.2 (2004): 389-394.

Peterfreund, Stuart. “Composing What May Not Be ‘Sad Trash’: A Reconsideration of

        Mary Shelley’s of Paracelsus in Frankenstein.” Studies in Romanticism 43

        (2004): 79-89.

Shelley, Mary. Frankenstein. J.M. Dent: Everyman, 1994.

Siniaia, M.S., et al., eds. “Habituation and desensitization of the Hering-Breuer Reflex in

        Rat.” The Journal of Physiology 523.2 (2000): 479-91.